Skip to main content
Engineering LibreTexts

2.5.2: Examples

  • Page ID
    10076
  • \( \newcommand{\vecs}[1]{\overset { \scriptstyle \rightharpoonup} {\mathbf{#1}} } \) \( \newcommand{\vecd}[1]{\overset{-\!-\!\rightharpoonup}{\vphantom{a}\smash {#1}}} \)\(\newcommand{\id}{\mathrm{id}}\) \( \newcommand{\Span}{\mathrm{span}}\) \( \newcommand{\kernel}{\mathrm{null}\,}\) \( \newcommand{\range}{\mathrm{range}\,}\) \( \newcommand{\RealPart}{\mathrm{Re}}\) \( \newcommand{\ImaginaryPart}{\mathrm{Im}}\) \( \newcommand{\Argument}{\mathrm{Arg}}\) \( \newcommand{\norm}[1]{\| #1 \|}\) \( \newcommand{\inner}[2]{\langle #1, #2 \rangle}\) \( \newcommand{\Span}{\mathrm{span}}\) \(\newcommand{\id}{\mathrm{id}}\) \( \newcommand{\Span}{\mathrm{span}}\) \( \newcommand{\kernel}{\mathrm{null}\,}\) \( \newcommand{\range}{\mathrm{range}\,}\) \( \newcommand{\RealPart}{\mathrm{Re}}\) \( \newcommand{\ImaginaryPart}{\mathrm{Im}}\) \( \newcommand{\Argument}{\mathrm{Arg}}\) \( \newcommand{\norm}[1]{\| #1 \|}\) \( \newcommand{\inner}[2]{\langle #1, #2 \rangle}\) \( \newcommand{\Span}{\mathrm{span}}\)\(\newcommand{\AA}{\unicode[.8,0]{x212B}}\)

    Let’s look at a few examples.

    Theorem 3.5.

    The number \(2^{2 n}\) − 1 is divisible by 3 for all natural numbers n.

    Proof. Here, P(n) is the statement that \(2^{2 n}\) − 1 is divisible by 3.
    Base case: When \(n=0,2^{2 n}-1=2^{0}-1=1-1=0\) and 0 is divisible by 3 (since 0 = 3 · 0.) Therefore the statement holds when n = 0.

    Inductive case: We want to show that if the statement is true for n = k (where k is an arbitrary natural number), then it is true for n = k + 1 also. That is, we must prove the implication \(P(k) \rightarrow P(k+1) .\) So we assume \(P(k),\) that is, we assume that \(2^{2 k}\) is divisible by \(3 .\) This means that \(2^{2 k}-1=3 m\) for some integer \(m .\) We want to prove \(P(k+1),\) that is, that \(2^{2(k+1)}-1\) is also divisible by \(3 :\)

    屏幕快照 2019-07-05 09.41.39.png

    and from the last line we see that \(2^{2 k+1}\) is in fact divisible by 3. (The third step-subtractin and adding 4—was done to enable us to use our inductive hypothesis.) Altogether, we have proved that P(0) holds and that, for all k, P(k) → P(k + 1) is true. Therefore, by the principle of induction, \(P(n)\) is true for all \(n\) in \(\mathbb{N},\) i.e. \(2^{2 n}-1\) is divisible by 3 for all n in N.

    The principle of mathematical induction gives a method for proving P(n) for all n in the set N. It should be clear that if M is any natural number, a similar method can be used to show that P(n) is true for all natural numbers n that satisfy n M. Just start the induction with a base case of n = M instead of with a base case of n = 0. I leave the proof of this extension of the principle of induction as an exercise. We can use the extended principle of induction to prove a result that was first mentioned in Section 2.1.

    Theorem 3.6.

    Suppose that a compound proposition contains exactly n propositional variables, where \(n \geq 1 .\) Then there are exactly \(2^{n}\) different ways of assigning truth walues to the n variables.

    Proof. Let P(n) be the statement “There are exactly \(2^{n}\) different ways of assigning truth values to n propositional variables.” We will use induction to prove the P(n) is true for all n ≥ 1.

    Base case: First, we prove the statement P(1). If there is exactly one variable, then there are exactly two ways of assigning a truth value to that variable. Namely, the variable can be either true or false. Since \(2=2^{1}, P(1)\) is true.

    Inductive case: Suppose that P(k) is already known to be true. We want to prove that, under this assumption, \(P(k+1)\) is also true. Suppose that \(p_{1}, p_{2}, \ldots, p_{k+1}\) are \(k+1\) propositional variables. Since we are assuming that P(k) is true, we know that there are \(2^{k}\) ways of assigning truth values to \(p_{1}, p_{2}, \dots, p_{k} .\) But each assignment of truth values to \(p_{1}, p_{2}, \ldots, p_{k}\) can be extended to the complete list \(p_{1}, p_{2}, \ldots, p_{k}, p_{k+1}\) in two ways. Namely, \(p_{k+1}\) can be assigned the value true or the value false. It follows that there are 2\(\cdot 2^{k}\) ways of assigning truth values to \(p_{1}, p_{2}, \ldots, p_{k+1} .\) since \(2 \cdot 2^{k}=2^{k+1},\) thishes the proof.


    2.5.2: Examples is shared under a not declared license and was authored, remixed, and/or curated by LibreTexts.

    • Was this article helpful?